Banner image

A Brief History of Literary Theory

Author: 
Chris Lang

Introduction

The question may naturally arise, "What has literary criticism to do with biblical studies?" Indeed the question is not a new one as Tertullian queried many years ago, "What has Athens to do with Jerusalem?" My response to the question is, "Everything." Because, however much we may lament it, the majority of the Western world lives not in Jerusalem but in Athens and in order to bring Jerusalem to Athens we must first bring Athens to Jerusalem. In other words, we must first understand the thinking of the modern world before we can speak meaningfully to it. In as much as literary theory is a reflection of modern thought, not to mention its implications for biblical criticism, it is worth endeavoring to understand it.

Another way to answer the original question is from a purely pragmatic viewpoint, as Kevin Vanhoozer has said, "For better or for worse, every form of literary criticism eventually finds at least one biblical exegete who is willing to be its champion." Footnote1 These words have shown true time and again. Post-modern literary theories are no exception. Post-structuralist theories such as reader-response theory and Deconstructionism have been gaining in popularity in biblical circles and it is these same post-modern theories that represent the greatest challenge to a grammatical-historical understanding of the text. To understand the challenge raised by these theories we must first survey the changes that have occurred in literary criticism in the recent past.

Literary theory has undergone drastic changes in the past century and this paper is an attempt to understand some of the influences that have altered the critical landscape. The change that has taken place in literary theory is not novel to this discipline alone, nor is it to be explained by any one phenomenon. The influences of modernism and post-modernism are accurately reflected in the changes that have taken place in literary theory.

To introduce the ideas of modernism as an influence on academia is to introduce a host of difficulties which are only exaggerated by the term post-modernism. The factors that have brought about what we call modernism are legion and cannot be attributed solely to either a change in philosophical thought or in sociological "development." There is a reciprocal relationship between these two phenomena. And both are necessary in order to understand the current situation. In the first chapter of this paper I will deal with the changes that have occurred in what is broadly referred to as literary theory, and more specifically with changes in the field of hermeneutics as it is this discipline that has most profoundly influenced literary theory recently. Specifically, I will focus on one post-structuralist critical theory, reader-response criticism as exemplified in the work of Stanley Fish. In the second chapter I will attempt to sketch the rise of modernism from the perspective of the history of ideas with special attention given to the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein as it relates to Fish. In the third chapter I will attempt the same goal from a sociological perspective, based primarily on the thought of Peter Berger. My purpose is to examine and attempt to explain reader-response criticism in light of post-modern thought.

Before proceeding it may be helpful to examine what is meant by the terms modernism and post-modernism. These are notoriously elusive terms which at times appear somewhat arbitrary as they often overlap and at times lack clear distinction. One of the difficulties encountered in elaborating on these terms is that there is no clear disjuncture between these two time periods or paradigms in thinking. Although many try, it is difficult to say exactly when modernism began and ended and when post-modernism has taken over. They are rather like rivers fed by many smaller streams so that while post-modernism may be said to be a late twentieth-century phenomenon, the ideas and sociological changes that have contributed to its rise may be traced back much further.

As there is little consensus regarding these terms, I will make a modest attempt to distinguish them. Modernism began with the rise of rationalism, in which man is viewed as the starting point for knowledge, and with the belief that truth can be ascertained chiefly through the scientific method. As a result of urbanization and the economic reordering of society there is a bifurcation between what is seen as public or social and what is held to be private. Increasingly, religious truth claims, individual morality, and meaning (whether it be that of a text or of life in general) are relegated to the latter, undergoing the same kind of privatization as capitalism has brought to property rights. Third, modernism shows a strong inclination toward individualism with its emphasis on freedom and the "existing" individual.

Post-modernism is in many ways, though not exclusively, a reaction against modernism. Post-modernism is characterized first by a rejection of foundational truth or ontological essentialism. Language is the primary means by which this belief is established as language is believed to be a social construct. Second, its individualism is pitted against any authoritarian structure or worldview that would stand over the individual. Third, post-modernism differs from modernism in the degree to which pluralism is experienced by the average person. As these phenomena have influenced culture, what people view as plausible has clearly changed.


Meaning: The Movement from 
Author to Reader

The image, it is clear, must be set between the mind or senses of the artist himself and the mind or senses of others. Stephen Dedalus

The most significant change that has occurred in the field of literary criticism and hermeneutics is in where the locus of meaning is perceived to inhere. In the disciplines of literary criticism and hermeneutics (when hermeneutics principally referred to the methods and rules of interpretation) it was originally assumed that meaning resided with the author. Thus the purpose of interpretation was to discern the author's intention which would unlock the textual meaning for all times. After Lessing, however, a new-found distance between the present and the past caused interpreters to focus more concertedly on the text itself, because the author was no longer deemed accessible to the interpreter. The shift in the locus of meaning continued under the influence of cultural pressures and meaning came to be seen as inhering in the reader.Footnote2 I can unfortunately select only a few individuals to mention in this brief survey of critical theory before focusing on one of the more prominent and radical reader-response critics, Stanley Fish.

The place to begin is in the discipline of theology with Friedrich Schleiermacher who sought to apply a scientific method of interpretation to the biblical texts. Gadamer attributes to him the differentiation of understanding and misunderstanding, in which the interpreter is seen to begin the process within his or her own misunderstandings.Footnote3 In other words, the interpreter brings to the text his own set of presuppositions which causes him to misunderstand the text. The hermeneutical method was intended to secure a right understanding of the text from preconceived understandings or misunderstandings. Thus there is a recognition that the mind does not necessarily act as a mirror reflecting exactly what is in the text. Schleiermacher's position is epistemologically more sophisticated than those preceding him. From this perspective the discipline of hermeneutics gradually moves from a methodological approach to the text toward the modern conception that hermeneutics is what happens when we interpret a text or how one comes to understanding.

The story of modern hermeneutics begins with Edmund Husserl and his phenomenological approach. Following "Descartes' dream" of absolute certainty in knowing, Husserl focused on things as they show themselves. The philosophy of this movement was to "let things appear as they are" or to refrain from reading our presuppositions into a text.Footnote4 The purpose of Husserl's "phenomenological reduction" is to focus on what is immediate to experience, "Everything not 'immanent' to consciousness must be rigorously excluded."Footnote5 In this approach the meaning of the text has been fixed by the language and exists in an "idealist" sense.

In an attempt to go beyond Husserl's essentialist approach, his pupil Martin Heidegger posited an existential theory of hermeneutics in Being and Time. Heidegger rejects the notion of objective historical knowledge, instead man finds himself "thrown into" the world in which language, culture and the institutions of life are givens. We cannot simply "bracket off" our pre-understanding in order to gain a transcendent, objective standpoint. Pure objectivity can never be gained by the subject. Heidegger's rejection of the subject-object, "I-it" duality leads him to the position of denying that meaning is fixed in a text which would be to affirm its objective reality. Thus meaning is not something objectifiable but is as elusive as Being itself.

Heidegger's Dasein or Being examines the situation of Being from within, not outside of, history. Being for Heidegger is the historically conditioned individual which is aware of itself and the passage of time. As Being exists in time its understanding is conditioned on previous understanding. Thus the interpreter finds himself in a hermeneutical circle in which prior understanding is always "read into" the process of understanding. Heidegger describes the circularity in the process of reasoning about Being in the following: "Phenomenological Interpretation must make it possible for Dasein itself to disclose things primordially; it must, as it were, let Dasein interpret itself."Footnote6

Truth is then seen, not as an objective grasp of meaning, but as the unveiling of Being through the medium of language.Footnote7 As Dasein is historically conditioned and understanding is based on prior understanding, interpretation for Heidegger is the extrapolation of past understanding into the future.

In interpretation, understanding does not become something different. It becomes itself. Such interpretation is grounded existentially in understanding; the latter does not arise from the former. Nor is interpretation the acquiring of information about what is to be understood; it is rather the working-out of possibilities projected in understanding.Footnote8

Although he thoroughly grasped the situation of pre-understanding, because he failed to understand the primacy of language in producing, not just expressing, meaning, Terry Eagleton calls his approach a "hermeneutic phenomenology."Footnote9

It was one of Heidegger's students, Hans-George Gadamer, who first presented an adequate view of linguistics in hermeneutical theory. Gadamer makes a nice transition figure between hermeneutics and literary theory for he was also a student of Rudolf Bultmann. Like Saussure and Wittgenstein, Gadamer argues that there is no thought prior to language. It is language that both makes possible and limits our understanding. "Gadamer would say," according to Brice Wachterhauser, "that it is only through language that we have a world."Footnote10 In order to understand a text we need a fusion between the horizon of our world and the world of the text. This is a creative or dialectic fusion which produces a new meaning.Footnote11 "To understand it does not mean primarily to reason one's way back into the past, but to have a present involvement in what is said."Footnote12 Gadamer represents a movement away from author-centered interpretation but there remains, however, a two-way process between text and interpreter in which the latter's questions are informed by the former. He explains in the following what is meant by a "fusion of horizons":

One intends to understand the text itself. But this means that the interpreter's own thoughts too have gone into re-awakening the text's meaning. In this the interpreter's own horizon is decisive, yet not as a personal standpoint that he maintains or enforces, but more as an opinion and a possibility that one brings into play and puts at risk, and that helps to truly make one's own what the text says.Footnote13

While Gadamer moved the locus of meaning from the author somewhere between the text and the reader, on the American scene in the early to mid-twentieth century we see the rise of a school focused solely on the text with New Criticism. Gadamer's own theories bear a number of similarities to the approach of New Criticism.Footnote14 I. A. Richards represents somewhat of a transitional figure to this movement. Eagleton comments that Richards "had naively assumed that the poem was no more than a ../graphics/cleardot medium through which we could observe the poet's psychological processes: reading was just a matter of recreating in our own mind the mental condition of the author. Indeed much traditional literary criticism has held this view in one form or another."Footnote15 With New Criticism we find the ascendancy of a more text-focused hermeneutic where the author's intention, even if it could be discerned, is irrelevant to the work at hand. The text is all that is and all that is important.

In text-centered literary criticism William Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley are key figures. It is their famous article on the "Intentional Fallacy" that secured the death of authorial intention. They argued that the psychological processes of the author are inaccessible to the interpreter. We are locked out of the mind of the author and have only the text and it is this that should be examined, not the author. As they wrote, "the design or intention of the author is neither available nor desirable as a standard for judging the success of a work of literary art."Footnote16 They continue in the same article by saying, "The poem is not the critic's own and not the author's (it is detached from the author at birth and goes about the world beyond his power to intend about it or control it). The poem belongs to the public" [italics mine].Footnote17 What is important to the New Critics is the verbal context as it now stands instead of the historical context in which it was first spoken. This may very well be a false dichotomy as it is unclear how the verbal context can have meaning apart from the historical context. But it is apparent that the wheels were in motion that transported meaning from the author's mental processes to that of the reader's, and the text from the public domain to the private.

It is Wimsatt and Beardsley who also bear the brunt of the later "reader-response" critics' ire. In another article on the Affective Fallacy, they argued against taking into consideration the affect which the text has on the reader saying that when this is done, "the poem itself, as an object . . . tends to disappear" making what was public verse into private verse.Footnote18 This comment also betrays the New Critical attempt to objectify the text and thus secure it from the subjectivity of those theories that had attempted to investigate what was happening in the mind of an author.

As with the neo-orthodox movement occurring in Germany, the meaning of the text is something that is not to be located in the past. There are definite similarities between New Criticism and German Neo-orthodoxy. The text is severed from its past and the interpreter stands at the far end of a yawning chasm with only the text in hand. It was Karl Barth who sought to free the meaning of the text from being corrupted by past understanding by positing an existential immediacy in which the Word is revealed to us through the word (recall Heidegger's "Being" revealed through the medium of language). Rudolf Bultmann then carried Barth's project to its radical extreme by severing all connections with the past in an attempt to secure meaning as suprahistorical.Footnote19 It is this mindset that is behind his demythologizing program which seeks to demonstrate "the independence of faith from history".Footnote20 Gadamer, on the other hand, sought to make immanent again the meaning by grounding it in language and Being. But if Gadamer moves us toward a text-centered hermeneutic, he also opens the door for the next movement in literary theory which is "reception theory."Footnote21

For Gadamer, because Dasein encounters the text in one's own world, the foundation of understanding is always shifting. Dasein is historically situated, which means that, "Our rational ability to make such judgments does not rest on some deep, permanent structure, transcendental reason or human nature, but rather it depends on our changing self-understanding."Footnote22 These insights open the door for a new attentiveness to the reader's contribution to the hermeneutic process. Eagleton notes that there has been, "a marked shift of attention to the reader over recent years. The reader has always been the most underprivileged of this trio [author, text, reader]--strangely, since without him or her there would be no literary texts at all."Footnote23

While the New Critics sought to secure the text objectively with verifiable results in the critical process, reader-response critics opened the door for the reader to focus on his or her mental processes in the act of reading. Following the German tradition, a more moderate proponent of this type of criticism is Wolfgang Iser. Iser says, "The phenomenological theory of art lays full stress on the idea that, in considering a literary work, one must take into account not only the actual text but also, and in equal measure, the actions involved in responding to that text." He goes on to say, "The convergence of text and reader brings the literary work into existence."Footnote24 Although Iser brings the reader more fully into the interpretive process, he does not find the locus of meaning to inhere in the reader. Similar to Gadamer's approach there is a free-play or creative act between the author and the reader with the reader supplying the gaps in understanding generated by the text.

A more radical approach to reader-response criticism in the tradition of neo-pragmatism and conventionalism is that of Stanley Fish. His assertion is that the reader manufactures the sense or meaning of the text. Meaning no longer inheres in the text, but is fully located within the reading community. Thus the reader's presuppositions are not something to be overcome, they are inescapable. The "interpretive community" is a reading public that shares a strategy or approach to interpretation. The text is not an object that can be approached and examined from the outside.Footnote25 There is no metanarrative; there is no truth or story that will encompass and make sense of all other narratives. There are only ungrounded language games and ungrounded interpretive communities. Indeed, a narrative is nothing without the reader. Fish rejects the idea that there are any right methodologies for interpretation; methodologies just are and they determine the interpretive results. He says that, "The meaning of an utterance, I repeat, is its experience--all of it--and that experience is immediately compromised the moment you say anything about it."Footnote26 At the end of this same article he concludes: "It follows then that what utterers do is give hearers and readers the opportunity to make meanings (and texts) by inviting them to put into execution a set of strategies."Footnote27


The Reader-Response Theory of Stanley Fish

He drew a circle that shut me out--

Heretic, rebel, a thing to flout:

But Love and I had the wit to win:

We drew a circle that took him in!

-Edwin Markham

At this point I would like to take a closer look at Stanley Fish's reader-response theory. It is my intent first to examine Fish's literary theory before criticizing it and then tie it in more broadly with the privatization of meaning and other phenomena occurring in philosophy and society which I will argue are historically conditioned. In other words, Fish's thesis is influenced by existential notions of truth and the rise of modernism/post-modernism.

There are really two kinds of reader-response criticism: one is a phenomenological approach to reading which characterizes much of Fish's earlier work, and the other is an epistemological theory characteristic of Fish's later work. The phenomenological method has much to commend itself to us as it focuses on what happens in the reader's mind as he or she reads. Fish applies this method in his early work "Surprised by Sin: The Reader in Paradise Lost." His thesis in this work is that Milton used a number of literary techniques intentionally to lead the reader into a false sense of security whereupon he would effect a turn from the reader's expectations in order to surprise the reader with his own prideful self-sufficiency. The supposed intent of Milton was to force the reader to see his own sinfulness in a new light and be forced back to God's grace. Fish's thesis is a rather ingenious approach to Paradise Lost and to Milton's (mis)leading of the reader.Footnote28

Fish's concern at this point in his career is with what "is really happening in the act of reading," and this is reflected in his compilations of essays entitled Is There a Text in This Class? especially the first half.Footnote29 Fish defines his own phenomenological approach as "an analysis of the developing responses of the reader in relation to the words as they succeed one another in time.Footnote30 His concern is with what the text does as opposed to what it means. As J. F. Worthen suggests, much of his work can be seen as a reaction against the formalism that characterized the age of New Critical theory which held that meaning was embedded in the textual artifact or, as Wimsatt and Beardsley referred to it, "the object".Footnote31 He suggests that, "The context for the discussion is the question of whether formal features exist prior to and independently of interpretive strategies."Footnote32 As one might imagine Fish eventually offers a negative response to this question. He posits that rather than having a text that contains formal features identifiable in all times and places that it is the reader that projects these features onto the text, thereby also answering "No" to the question, "Is there a text in this class?"

From this point in Fish's career his theories evolve into a form of criticism that rejects the author's intentionally and places meaning solely within the arena of those receiving the text. Thus his theory is sometimes called "reception aesthetics" or "affective stylistics." Fish claims that it is the interpretive community that creates its own reality. It is the community that invests a text, or for that matter life itself, with meaning. Those who claim that meaning is to be found in some eternal superstructure or substructure of reality he labels "foundationalists." Naturally, because foundationalists comprise their own interpretive communities and interpret through such a grid, they will be opposed to theories such as his own. His theory is epistemological in that it deals not so much with literary criticism (although the implications for such are tremendous) as with how one comes to know. In the following analysis of Fish's theory I will focus primarily on his later reader-response theory.


Meaning in the Reader

This aspect of Fish's theory is one of the most radical and controversial. He posits that meaning inheres not in the text but in the reader, or rather the reading community. "In the procedures I would urge," he writes, "the reader's activities are at the center of attention, where they are regarded not as leading to meaning but as having meaning."Footnote33 He can hold this because he believes that there is no stable basis for meaning. There is no correct interpretation that will always hold true. Meaning does not exist "out there" somewhere. It exists, rather, within the reader.

In his earlier work he made a claim, not wholly disavowed in his later material, that what a text means is the experience that it produces in the reader. To define meaning he says, "It is an experience; it occurs; it does something; it makes us do something. Indeed, I would go so far as to say, in direct contradiction of Wimsatt and Beardsley, that what it does is what it means."Footnote34 Here Fish stakes out the territory of his critical enterprise which is to set himself against the formalist principles of the past with its supposed scientific agenda. This project he admits took some time from which to effect a complete liberation. But this is the principle that will eventually lead his theory from (what his critics would call) an "objective" to a fully blown "subjective" interpretive theory. Indeed, his early theory appears to be completely vulnerable to the criticism of subjectivity as he posits an experiential dimension to meaning which inheres in "the active and activating consciousness of the reader," a charge he will later attempt to counter.Footnote35

Fish's next move in his anti-formalist agenda is to deny the text as object, which was so important to Wimsatt and Beardsley and the New Critics. "The objectivity of the text is an illusion and, moreover, a dangerous illusion, because it is so physically convincing."Footnote36 What exactly Fish means by this statement is somewhat unclear. He does not, as it may appear, deny the ontological reality or the existence of the palpable object, although one could argue that that is exactly what this sentence by itself means because he apparently pairs the word "objective" with "physical."Footnote37 It is the context that illuminates what he is driving at. But he does deny the text's independence as a repository of meaning.Footnote38 The text does not contain meaning: despite being written upon, it is a tabula rasa, a blank slate onto which the reader, in reading, actually writes the text.

Fish takes the idea of the hermeneutical circle seriously. The reader is always reading her preunderstanding back into the text with no possibility of achieving an "objective" or author-centered interpretation. Fish claims that an interpretive theory is itself circular, that the interpreter will always find what he is looking for in the text, that formal patterns "are themselves constituted by an interpretive act."Footnote39 He claims at one point that:

Theories always work and they will always produce exactly the results they predict, results that will be immediately compelling to those for whom the theory's assumptions and enabling principles are self-evident. Indeed, the trick would be to find a theory that didn't work.Footnote40

Because the assumptions one begins with will determine the outcome of the study, for Fish, "success is inevitable."Footnote41 The methods with which one approaches the text have already determined the outcome, one's presuppositions actuate the product.Footnote42

For Fish a text is only a RorschachFootnote43 blot onto which the reader projects her self-understanding or, as we shall see, her culturally determined assumptions. The text contains nothing in itself, rather the content is supplied by the reader. It is the reader that determines the shape of text, its form, and its content. This is how Fish can claim that reader's write texts. Worthen's comment is apt. He says, "as far as Fish is concerned, reading can only repeat reality, in that it necessarily consists of nothing but replications of independently existing collective interpretive strategies."Footnote44 This is exactly what reading does and this is one of the difficulties of his theory. It fails to account for the text being able to expand the readers' understanding or Weltanshung by introducing her to a different way of perceiving. For Fish the text can only function as a mirror that provides a reflection of its reader.


Authorial Intent

It is in this same manner that Fish dismisses the idea of authorial intent as the guiding principle in interpretation. In analyzing one of his previous critical works he declares,

I did what critics always do: I "saw" what my interpretive principles permitted or directed me to see, and then I turned around and attributed what I had 'seen' to a text and an intention. . . . What I am suggesting is that formal units are always a function of the interpretive model one brings to bear; they are not "in" the text, and I would make the same argument for intentions.Footnote45

To claim that the author intended to say or do such and such is really a declaration regarding the interpreter, in Fish's theory. Thus different interpreters will see different intentions because they are a creation of the reader and not the author. As with New Critical theory, the author fails to live past the creation of the text, indeed, for Fish the author as well is a creation of the reader.Footnote46

Fish can make this move because of his epistemic beliefs that nothing we see, perceive, or think is uninterpreted. He considers the attempt to access the author's intention as naive; for how would one ever access an intention as it does not exist in any objective or uninterpreted realm that can be mediated to our consciousness without itself being interpreted? We could have access to documents regarding the author's true intention, "but the documents . . . that would give us that intention are no more available to a literal reading (are no more uninterpreted) than the literal reading it would yield." Thus when John writes, "These things have been written that you might believe that Jesus is the Christ, the son of God; and that believing you may have eternal life in his name," we are no closer to his intentions than were he to have said and written nothing.Footnote47

Fish is following after the New Critical school, which as we have seen, disregarded authorial intent as well as historical interpretation. For Fish it is not important to access the original context in order to access meaning. He says, "to consult dictionaries, grammars, and histories is to assume that meanings can be specified independently of the activity of reading."Footnote48 But as we have seen it is the activity of reading which takes center stage in the making of meaning. Fish posits this because he believes that we as interpreters are cut off from past worlds or cultures. In other words, he believes that we are without commonality with past cultures and that, therefore, a complete disjuncture exists. The interpreter belongs to a different world from the author.


Interpretive Communities

What lies behind Fish's thinking at this point is a strong view of the social construction of reality. Fish firmly believes that knowledge is not objective but always socially conditioned. All that one thinks and "knows" is an interpretation that is only made possible by the social context in which one lives. For Fish the very thoughts one thinks are made possible by presuppositions of the community in which one lives and furthermore the socially conditioned individual, which all individuals are, cannot think beyond the limits made possible by the culture. This culture is referred to by Fish as an "interpretive community" and the strategies of an interpreter are

community property, and insofar as they at once enable and limit the operations of his consciousness, he is too [community property]. . . . Interpretive communities are made up of those who share interpretive strategies not for reading but for writing texts, for constituting their properties.Footnote49

Fish believes that interpretive communities, like languages, are purely conventional, that is, arbitrarily agreed upon constructions. The way a community lives is in no way a reflection of some higher reality, it is rather a construction, or edifice that has been erected by consensus. This holds true for the interpretive strategies a culture or an institution employs as well as their notions of right and wrong. A culture's morality is no more founded in any external reality than its language.Footnote50 Nor is it possible to specify how language correlates with the external world.Footnote51 Language and its usage are arbitrary decisions made by convention as is the fact that we call north "North" instead of something else.

In response to a criticism launched by M. H. Abrams, Fish explains some of his understanding of the conventional nature of language.

If what follows is communication or understanding, it will not be because he and I share a language, in the sense of knowing the meanings of individual words and the rules for combining them, but because a way of thinking, a form of life, shares us, and implicates us in a world of already-in-place objects, purposes, goals, procedures, values, and so on; and it is to the features of that world that any words we utter will be heard as necessarily referring [italics mine].Footnote52

Similarly, what we call literature is not such because of some abiding principle of truth or art that exists in an atemporal state, but it is such because the culture values it for interests of its own, that is because it reflects the culture's values and beliefs in some way.

Thus the act of recognizing literature is not constrained by something in the text, nor does it issue from an independent and arbitrary will; rather, it proceeds from a collective decision as to what will count as literature, a decision that will be in force only so long as a community of readers or believers continues to abide by it.Footnote53

In this view literature is simply the expression of an ideology. Because of his views on literature, literature tends to lose its "special status" as literature and becomes simply a reflection of communal values which is as subject to change as are cultures. That is not to say that the individual or culture consciously chooses its values, which would imply some form of objectivity or the ability to stand apart from one's values. To Fish it is not possible to abstract one's self from one's values. Fish is simply a product of his environment without the ability to choose his beliefs and values. They are instead informed or determined by the culture which is historically conditioned and no more able to choose objectively than the individual.

Using Fish as an example of post-structuralist critical theory, I will in the remaining chapters analyze his thought as it relates to post-modernism. What follows is an examination of post-modernism from the perspective of the discipline of philosophy, or an history of ideas approach. It is not intended to be a comprehensive history of Western philosophy but a brief examination of some of the salient features which I believe have contributed to the rise of what is now being called post-modernism. I will end the chapter with an emphasis on the "linguistic turn", as Rorty has called it, in philosophy of the twentieth century by examining some of the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein as his thinking bears some similarities to that of Stanley Fish and lays some of the groundwork for the current state of things. Wittgenstein is important as his thinking is often characterized as thoroughly conventionalist and misappropriated as such.

In the following chapters I would also like to take a critical look at some of Fish's theory and examine some of the consequences of his thinking. Fish claims that because his thinking is theoretical it is without consequences (he consistently tells his critics "not to worry"). He is at least disingenuous if not patently dishonest in this assertion as his theories have grave consequence especially for those who would appeal to some transcendent standard.

In taking a critical stance toward Fish's literary theory I am well aware of Fish's response to those who disagree with his theories or, as he puts it, "feel threatened" by his ideas. Those who hold to the idea of essences, or to the reality and accessibility of transcendent truths, he labels as foundationalists, members of the "intellectual right."Footnote54 And he further accuses them of holding to a naive epistemology which views the mind as merely reflecting the world as it really is (an sich). Footnote55 Moreover they are characterized as without understanding how fundamental language is to one's world view and the cultural assumptions that go with it. I must plead guilty to being a foundationalist with objections to Fish's theory. Fish claims that his theory, however, is internally coherent, while I will argue just the opposite, that his theory does not cohere based on his own assumptions. Fish's response to these criticisms would be to deny me as his critic access to his theory in the first place because I do not share his assumptions and, to him, only those who are within a community can understand its thought. That claim is, however, as we shall see, one of the bases of my criticism. Let us turn briefly to the history of philosophy.


Post-Modernism And The
History Of Ideas

In the republic of scholarship, every citizen has a constitutional right to get himself as thoroughly lost as he pleases. David Hackett Fischer

 

There it is, the unbearable lightness of being. 
Milan Kundera

One of the approaches in examining post-modernism is to delineate the changes in philosophy or the history of ideas. From this perspective modernism is seen as a phenomenon stressing rationalism based on the universal design or concept which gives order to a reality that can be known through the appropriate, that is scientific, method. It also stresses an optimistic faith in mankind's uniqueness and ability to progress. Post-modernism, on the other hand, emphasizes the lack of foundation in knowledge, the rootedness of understanding in language and context, as well as a rejection of the idea that "man" is at the center of the universe. In many ways post-modernism can be seen as an extension of modernism as the ideas of the one are rooted in the other. I will attempt a brief synopsis of this in the following pages.


From the Enlightenment to Existentialism: 
Existence Over Essence

Many trace the rise of modernism in philosophy to Descartes' process of radical doubt. His intent was to place knowledge on a secure foundation. To do this he methodologically is called into question everything he felt he knew and discovered that almost everything could be questioned. Descartes ended his doubt, or found bedrock on the tenuous foundation of his own consciousness. His own inner cognition was the only thing of which he could be certain. Cogito ergo sum (I think therefore I am) is his final declaration. While his intention was to find certainty in knowing, Descartes radically changed epistemology by introducing his methodological doubt, a process which did not always end where Descartes had ended.

Though few agreed with Descartes' assertion, none were left unaffected by it. His cogitation began a shift in the way people perceived and experienced reality. The modern paradigm brought with it a search for objectivity established on the tenuous foundations of the individual consciousness. Descartes prompted both the relentless pursuit of the "objective" as well as planting the seeds of its demise. Kierkegaard perceptively identifies this subjective turn as early as 1843 in his publication of Fear and Trembling. He says,

Descartes has not cried 'Fire!' and made it everyone's duty to doubt, for Descartes was a quiet and lonely thinker, not a bellowing streetwatch; he was modest enough to allow that his method was important only for himself [italics mine] and sprang partly from his own earlier bungling with knowledge. ("Thus my design here is not to teach the Method which everyone should follow in order to promote the good conduct of Reason, but only to show in what manner I have endeavored to conduct my own . . .").Footnote56

Whereas Hegel would later attempt to encompass all of reality in his system, according to Kierkegaard, Descartes' intentions were much more modest.

The shift in epistemological method and certainty is at the heart of what is referred to as modernism and post-modernism. The Enlightenment project sought to replace divine revelation with human reason. Empiricism and scientific method were seen as the proper means of gaining access to truth, which is considered knowable within this paradigm. The human individual took center stage. In the post-Descartes world, however, knowledge was perceived to be an increasingly subjective endeavor, which is ironic as he sought to ground knowledge objectively. Lesslie Newbigin sees the Enlightenment mentality as a relentless pursuit of the critical method. "But the critical method must ultimately destroy itself. You cannot criticize a statement of what claims to be the truth except on the basis of some other truth-claim which -- at that moment -- you accept without criticism. But that truth-claim on which your critique is based must in turn be criticized" says Newbigin.Footnote57

While rationalism has reigned supreme from Descartes' time to our own, it has not been without its detractors. The Romantic movement in English and German literature is one of them. Reacting against the sterility and mechanization of all of life including that of religion, as evidenced by Deism, the Romantics sought to affirm the dynamic nature of the universe against the cold, rational system.Footnote58 Romanticism reemphasized the central place of the individual and sought to free the unconscious mind. Existentialism is another form of rebellion against rationalism and it shares a number of similarities with Romanticism. Frederick Copleston assesses the situation nicely when he says, "Hegel sought to capture all reality in the conceptual net of his dialectic, while existence slipped through the meshes."Footnote59 Existentialism reacted against any kind of a universal system or ethical absolute (especially Hegel's metaphysical system) that stands above the individual. The existential psychologist Rollo May summarizes it aptly:

Existentialism means centering upon the existing person; it is the emphasis on the human being as he is emerging, becoming. The word "existence" comes from the root ex-sistere, meaning literally "to stand out, emerge." Traditionally in Western culture, existence has been set over against essence, the latter being the emphasis upon immutable principles, truth, logical laws, etc., that are supposed to stand above any given existence.Footnote60

After existentialism existence gains primacy over essence with the emphasis placed primarily on the individual actualizing his or her existence through choice. Truth is experienced as an inward passion or the recovery of Being as opposed to an immutable principle. As Kierkegaard put it, "An objective uncertainty held fast in an appropriation-process of the most passionate inwardness is the truth, the highest truth attainable for an existing individual" [italics his].Footnote61 I would argue that to the extent that existentialism has succeeded in overthrowing the universal or "essence," the demise of the idea of "absolute truth" has been the result. However, the loss of essence eventually results in the loss of existence with its resultant "unbearable lightness of being."Footnote62 Being no longer has meaning. This state naturally leads to philosophical relativism a condition which is exaggerated by the theories of language that follow. Gene Edward Veith rightly concludes, "Existentialism is the philosophical basis for postmodernism."Footnote63

Stanley Fish, as a post-modern literary theorist, also reflects a dependence on existentialist thought including that of Gadamer in his writings. While his emphasis on what a text does versus what it means may be primarily indebted to pragmatism, the idea of "meaning as an event," is thoroughly existential. Fish reflects the existential priority of the human consciousness as it brings to prominence the existing individual with its focus on experience. Often he characterizes meaning as an experience in opposition to an essence or truth located outside of the individual reader. "In the procedures I would urge, the reader's activities are at the center of attention, where they are regarded not as leading to meaning but as having meaning."Footnote64 And he makes an uncouched declaration regarding the nature of man by contrasting the Stylistics (formalist) approach, which is rooted in empiricism and positivism, with his own by declaring the former unworthy, "for it would deny to man the most remarkable of his abilities, the ability to give the world meaning rather than to extract a meaning that is already there."Footnote65 Fish apparently feels his philosophical freedom threatened by those practitioners who came before him.

But much of Fish's theoretical position can be seen as reactionary when viewed against the backdrop of philosophical modernism, by which I mean the Enlightenment project with its quest for absolute certainty and scientific objectivity. In Fish's thinking, as well as that of most post-modern thinkers, objectivity is an illusion brought about by the Enlightenment for which Descartes often takes the blame. Existence stands over essence and then essentialism or foundationalism, as Fish would call it, loses its independence and becomes dependant on the individual's experience. Fish claims that his formalist predecessors assumed that there were "observable facts that could be described and interpreted."Footnote66 But he argues that what counts as a fact is in itself determined by the presupposition of the interpreter thereby invalidating the entire procedure.

In an article published a few years later, Fish (who must be applauded for having the courage of being logically consistent even if it is illogical) gives up on evidence altogether including evidence that might support his position, "But it is the very possibility of providing such evidence that is denied [in this paper]. . . . I cut myself off from any recourse to evidentiary procedures."Footnote67 At this point one wonders what is the purpose of publishing papers if it is not to propound opinions and arguments, which amounts to the same thing as giving evidence. It is Fish's opinion that objectivity is an illusion, but as with making a claim to relativism, anytime one argues for a position he then stakes a claim to knowledge and anytime one stakes a claim to knowledge a claim to objectivity or truth is implicit.


The Linguistic Turn

Peter Berger argues that "reality is socially constructed, and therefore that truth over and beyond these social constructions cannot easily be attained."Footnote68 The last half of the statement is what separates Berger from Fish and post-modern thought. While he holds to a "metanarrative", a belief that there is a truth that makes sense of reality, post-modern thought is characterized by the belief that our experience of reality is a function of our language which is socially determined. Ludwig Wittgenstein proposed that our "language games" are a reflection of our "forms of life." By this he means that a language rests on the way we do things in the world. Wittgenstein said, "You must bear in mind that the language-game is so to say something unpredictable. I mean; it is not based on grounds. It is not reasonable (or unreasonable). It is there--like our life."Footnote69 Wittgenstein would contend that the center of language, far from being an eternal logoV, is the constantly shifting and dynamic "forms of life," the activities, purpose, and context in which language games are played.

For Wittgenstein there is no essence of language, it is not a logocentric, metalinguistic idea. The thought here is similar to Derrida's concept of "de-centering" language.Footnote70 There is no ontological reality, no presence to language. It is not grounded in a metaphysical reality but in the context and function of life. Derrida argues that Western thought has functioned from a belief in a "presence" or ontology that is beyond or above.

It would be possible to show that all the names related to fundamentals, to principles, or to the center have always designated the constant of a presence--eidosarchetelosenergeiaousia. . . aletheia, transcendentality, consciousness, or conscience, God, man, and so forth."Footnote71

His purpose is to "de-center" language from the idea of "being" to that of "function." In other words, language is a pragmatic, ungrounded web of signifiers which constantly points not to any reality beyond but only to itself. The refusal to recognize these facts Derrida calls logocentrism.Footnote72

In postmodern thought logocentric discourse is considered totalizing, authoritarian discourse. It is at this point that Nietzsche's idea of the "will to power" enters the discussion in that as much as any one perspective claims knowledge, there exists a will to power. Jane P. Tompkins states,

The insistence that language is constitutive of reality rather than merely reflective of it suggests that contemporary critical theory has come to occupy a position very similar to, if not the same as, that of the Greek rhetoricians for whom mastery of language meant mastery of the state. . . . The similarity lies rather in the common perception of language as a form of power.Footnote73

From this perspective reason itself is seen to be an ideology that is Western and totalitarian.

For literary theorists and philosophers the conclusion is clear: the one who controls the language controls the world. For Marxist, African-American, and feminist critics this means the white middle class bourgeoisie and represents an order which must be challenged. Julia Kristeva, a Freudian feminist critic and philosopher, "looks to this 'language' of the semiotic as a means of undermining the symbolic order," in Eagleton's words. Referring to her language, he continues,

It is opposed to all fixed, transcendental signification's; and since the ideologies of modern male-dominated class-society rely on such fixed signs for their power (God, father, state, order, property and so on), such literature becomes a kind of equivalent in the realm of language to revolution in the sphere of politics.Footnote74

From this perspective, it is not surprising that the "Great Books" tradition has fallen out of favor in university curricula.

So the question becomes, not whether language holds power, but who will control language.Footnote75 It is to this end that we find competing ideologies in literature, theory, and philosophy. Jane Tompkins comments, "When discourse is responsible for reality and not merely a reflection of it, then whose discourse prevails makes all the difference."Footnote76 Thus we find in the academy today what has been termed a "culture war" as each element in a pluralistic society struggles to win strategic points of the landscape on which to plant their educational flag.Footnote77

While the existentialists took up where Descartes began with a focus on truth as a subjective phenomenon, modern literary theory has taken the idea one step further. Because language is not a reflection of a transcendent "word", but a completely immanent, functional medium, the very idea of truth collapses. Eagleton says it well,

The work of Derrida and others had cast grave doubt upon the classical notions of truth, reality, meaning and knowledge, all of which could be exposed as resting on a naively representational theory of language. If meaning, the signified, was a passing product of words or signifiers, always shifting and unstable, part-present and part-absent, how could there be any determinate truth or meaning at all?Footnote78

The rejection of any kind of metanarrative, as we have seen with Derrida, places reason itself in jeopardy because rational systems, and especially those with which we are familiar in the West, produce yet another kind of totalizing discourse that merely serves to justify the society in which it operates. "The hermeneutics of suspicion sees every text as a political creation, usually designed to function as propaganda for the status quo," according to Veith.Footnote79

Fish reflects this anti-rationalism in his writing first by denying literature any special status, as we have seen in his work, and also by propounding a "controlled subjectivity" as opposed to an objectivity. Nietzsche claimed that, "truths are illusions of which one has forgotten that they are illusions." And, "he speaks most truthfully who recognizes the illusory nature of his speech."Footnote80 Fish echoes this sentiment when he writes, "I would rather have an acknowledged and controlled subjectivity than an objectivity which is finally an illusion."Footnote81 It is worth asking how one can have any control over subjectivity, either in the individual or the interpretive community, where objectivity is impossible. We will take this point up again in the next chapter, but for now let us underscore Fish's unwillingness to endorse reason as anything other than an historically conditioned ideology.

That is to say, unless one argues (as I shall finally argue) that the rational is itself a historical category. . . fashioned and refashioned by. . . causal forces. . . the rational will inevitably be seen as a category that is transhistorical and therefore as a category that is finally independent of the "causal" forces that either nourish it or threaten it.Footnote82

I think it safe to say that Fish's theory is intended to threaten rationality as his theoretical claim holds that literature, language, and rational categories are conventional and not foundational.

At this point it might be helpful to back up and examine more carefully one of the philosophers responsible for the linguistic turn in current theory, Ludwig Wittgenstein. Stanley Fish's thought shows familiarity with Wittgenstein's writing. He references Wittgenstein's terms such as form of life, language games, the conventional nature of language, and stresses the importance of meaning being associated with the context of an activity.Footnote83 The latter of these concepts is certainly not exclusive to Wittgenstein, but I believe that Fish's concept of an interpretive community is derived, at least partially, from a misappropriated concept of this Austrian philosopher.Footnote84 I will attempt to flesh out Wittgenstein's thought, compare it with Fish's and examine the differences.


The Philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein

"In the beginning was the deed."
-Faust

In order to gain a better understanding of the origins of much of modern thinking which regards language and truth as conventional it will be necessary to spend some time examining Ludwig Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein is an often misunderstood and misapplied philosopher who while postulating the conventional nature of language, still held to an objectivist view of truth. The philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein may seem at first to have little to do with the hermeneutical thinkers of the existentialist school, in as much as he is often mistakenly labeled as part of the Logical Positivist movement. Although his earlier work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, was hailed by the Vienna Circle, Wittgenstein never felt they understood him and was hesitant to ally himself with this movement. A hesitancy which eventually culminated in a complete reworking of his earlier thought. In his later work, Philosophical Investigations, he further distanced himself from this group. It is difficult to place Wittgenstein within a school as he has been variously associated with a number of different schools. Therefore to categorize Wittgenstein solely with the Anglo-American, Continental, or Logical Positivists would seem to be misguided.

Recent commentators on Literary Theory and Hermeneutics invariably quote from Philosophical Investigations and compare his thought favorably with that of Saussure, Heidegger, and Gadamer. And there has been a sustained effort recently to graft Wittgenstein's thought into the tree from which the modern hermeneutical discussion blossoms.Footnote86

To begin this discussion it is necessary to briefly sketch some elements of Wittgenstein's language theory. He approaches both philosophy and language from a descriptive standpoint and to this end I believe his language theory can be divided into two primary parts. First, language is for Wittgenstein functional or pragmatic in that he posits a "use theory" of language. For Wittgenstein language is what it does (recall Fish). There is no essence to language. It is system of conventional signs. Second, language has a social foundation. What he calls "forms of life" are what undergird his language theory. It follows from this that public criterion is essential to a language and conversely, that there can be no purely private language games. I will elaborate on these ideas in what follows.


Language as Convention

Wittgenstein demonstrates his pragmatic approach to language throughout the Investigations. In one of the more celebrated quotes he says, "For philosophical problems arise when language goes on holiday."Footnote87 By "goes on holiday" I take him to mean that when language is "idle." When it is not functioning is when we have the most difficulty with language because without a functional dimension language is nonsensical.Footnote88 For Wittgenstein language is always practical. It is intended to do something. The very idea of intending presupposes a purpose. He says, "without language we cannot influence other people in such-and-such ways; cannot build roads and machines, etc. . ."Footnote89 For Wittgenstein language is a tool. And a tool may be used in any number of ways some of which are legitimate and some are not. He likens a sentence to an instrument and its meaning, the employment we give it.Footnote90 As such our language is a large toolbox with many instruments at our disposal and these instruments have various uses.

From this general approach Wittgenstein's "Usage Theory" of language arises. Again his approach is seen to be descriptive. He maintains that in most cases, "the meaning of a word is its use in the language."Footnote91 In other words, we do not ascribe definitions to words in a hierarchical fashion, instead their meaning is determined by their usage, by the conventions of the language users. Thus context is essential in determining meaning. "Let the use of words teach you their meaning."Footnote92 And because language is conventional, because the meaning of a word is determined by its use in the language, it is a constantly changing phenomenon. Wittgenstein compares language to a city with old streets and new, with decrepit sections and developing suburbs.Footnote93 "And this multiplicity is not something fixed, given once for all; but new types of language, new language-games, as we may say, come into existence, and others become obsolete and get forgotten."Footnote94 Because there is not a fixed, determined essence of language that has been given once for all, there is potentially an infinite number of language games.

The idea of "language game" (Sprachspiel) is possibly the best known aspect of Wittgenstein's thought. By language game Wittgenstein means an independent set of linguistic symbols with their corresponding actions used by a group of people possibly as large as a nation or as small as two. A builder and his assistant may have their own peculiar language game which, though it is independent, overlaps other language games.Footnote95 The language of science and the language of religion, while they may share some words and actions, are different language games with differing purposes as well as differing "kinds" of certainty. This does not mean that the scientist and the religious adherent cannot communicate and interact, they can. But the purpose of each one's language game differs even though they overlap. Words bear "family resemblances" as they are interrelated phenomena. We could just as well say that language games also bear these resemblances. The importance of this will be seen as we turn again to the thought of Stanley Fish. Each word bears a relationship to other words in this language game as well as to other language games depending on the conventions employed.Footnote96

Because words are used by convention there is then a certain arbitrariness to the symbols (written and verbal) that are associated with concepts in our world. Here the linguistic ontology of Western philosophy since the time of Plato comes under attack and modern philosophy has not been the same since. Wittgenstein's theory of language is anti-essentialist. He says, "We are under the illusion that what is peculiar, profound, essential in our investigation, resides in its trying to grasp the incomparable essence of language. . . . Whereas, of course, if the words 'language', 'experience', 'world', have a use, it must be as humble a one as that of the words 'table', 'lamp', 'door'."Footnote97 There is no metaphysical nature of language. There is no single fibre running through the entire thread.Footnote98

Why do we call something a 'number': Well, perhaps because it has a--direct--relationship with several things that have hitherto been called number; and this can be said to give it an indirect relationship to other things we call the same name. And we extend our concept of number as in spinning a thread we twist fibre on fibre. And the strength of the thread does not reside in the fact that some one fibre runs through its whole length, but in the overlapping of the fibres.Footnote99

When Wittgenstein says that there is no metaphysical nature of language, however, he does not mean, as the logical positivists supposed and the post-moderns affirm, that there is no such thing as a metaphysical realm. Even in the Tractatus, Wittgenstein would say that it may be there, it is just the kind of thing of which we cannot speak.Footnote100


Forms of Life

The second aspect of Wittgenstein's language theory, which is inexorably connected with the first, is that language has a social foundation. Language games for him are not a disconnected web of symbols but have their grounding in what he refers to as "forms of life." Nicholas F. Gier says that it is clearly a mistake to identify "Lebensformen and language games" as has often been done.Footnote101 Because the importance of this point cannot be minimized I will therefore demonstrate it by a number of references to his later works. Continuing section 23 cited earlier from Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein elaborates, "Here the term 'language-game' is meant to bring into prominence the fact that the speaking of language is part of an activity, or of a form of life." He says that a language game is a part of, though not equal to, a form of life. The words we exchange and the use we put them to is dependant on the life context in which we operate. As we will see Fish makes use of this idea. They are for this reason a priori they are the givens of any situation.

In his typically enigmatic fashion, Wittgenstein says, "Thought is surrounded by a halo.--Its essence, logic, presents an order, in fact the a priori order of the world: that is, the order of possibilities, which must be common to both world and thought."Footnote102 Wittgenstein is maintaining that there is a correspondence between the given world and the thought or language we employ to act upon it, otherwise thought, communication, and action in the world would be impossible.Footnote103 The Investigations does not maintain, in arguing against the Tractatus, that there is no correspondence between language and the world as Derrida might argue, only that the correspondence is different than that of the picture theory. But this given's of language games is not a logocentric, metalinguistic idea. Wittgenstein would contend that the center of language is the constantly shifting and dynamic "forms of life."

"What has to be accepted, the given, is--so one could say--forms of life."Footnote104 We live in a common world and that commonality allows us to communicate about the world. Again, he maintains in On Certainty:

"An empirical proposition can be tested" (we say). But how? and through what?

What counts as its test?--"But is this an adequate test? And, if so, must it not be recognizable as such in logic?"--As if giving grounds did not come to an end sometime. But the end is not an ungrounded presupposition: it is an ungrounded way of acting.Footnote105

Grounds do come to an end, as doubting does. The end it comes to is our way of acting or our "forms of life." The forms of life are the a priori, the given. And these forms of life differ depending on time and place and consequently the language games reflect this changing nature. Fish takes this principle regarding language and, I believe, misapplies it to interpretive communities resulting in a constantly shifting and groundless community.


Public Criterion and Private Languages

Under the general classification that language has its foundation in a social context or form of life, are two closely related ideas, that of public criterion and the argument against private languages. Wittgenstein argues against the idea that there can be a language of one. Because languages are based on forms of life, they must relate to the external world.

The problem with the hypothetical "private language" is that it cannot conform to "forms of life." It cannot conform itself to the external world for the very reason that it is private. And anything that is to be called a language must be demonstrable in the external world. In other words, something must be observable for us to be able to verify that we are all speaking of the same phenomenon. "An 'inner process' stands in need of outward criteria."Footnote106 The difficulty with the private language idea is that there exists no external phenomenon by which we can measure the inner sensation.

We might apply this idea to the concept of authorial intent. We simply cannot get inside another's mind to demonstrate or show what is that person's intent. And here Wittgenstein has shown philosophers the way out of the fly bottle. It is not a matter of seeing into someone, but rather seeing what is public. "An 'inner process' stands in need of outward criteria."Footnote107 The inner process, "meaning" is in need of the public criteria of text. But Wittgenstein goes further than just asserting the necessity for an explicit expression of intent. "Thus the most explicit expression of intention is by itself insufficient evidence of intention."Footnote108 We can recall Fish's statement which is similar. The difference I think is that Wittgenstein would claim that the utterance or text and the act which went with it, its context, is sufficient outward criteria to demonstrate intention. Intention moves out of the jurisdiction of the private language critique when associated with outward criteria, that is with actions and utterances and texts. But Fish's problem with authorial intent lies at a more fundamental level and it has to do with interpretive communities. We will turn to this idea next.


Comparison: Or Isolated Communities

If a lion could talk, we could not understand him. Ludwig Wittgenstein

One of the most serious consequences of Fish's interpretive community theory is that it severs communication across cultural and historical boundaries. This is a result of his anti-essentialist position. Fish claims that "intention and understanding are two ends of a conventional act, each of which necessarily stipulates (includes, defines, specifies) the other."Footnote109 What this means is that without being part of the interpretive community in which the act is done, spoken, uttered we have no access to its "intention" nor do we have "understanding." Thus we are sealed off from the utterances of history, bound to interpret them based on our cultural assumptions and unable to penetrate into the mindset of the past. This is a radical reduction of worldview that Fish would have us confined within. The results of such a theory leave closed the possibility of enlarging one's understanding based on the presuppositions of a foreign culture, with the possible exception of actually being a part of that culture. While his determinism maintains that we can understand only what our culture makes available, any broadened perspective is then by default already encompassed within the assumptions of our interpretive community.

Fish claims that "communication only occurs within a community." The question then becomes how to join that community in order to communicate. In postulating a radical distance between communities Fish writes:

Nor would it be enough to give someone "on the outside" a set of definitions because in order to grasp the meaning of an individual term, you must already have grasped the general activity in relation to which it could be thought to be meaningful. . . . an understanding that operates above or across situations--would have no place in the world even if it were available, because it is only in situations--with their interested specifications as to what counts as a fact, what it is possible to say, what will be heard as an argument--that one is called on to understand.Footnote110

He is in agreement with Wittgenstein as far as using proofs appropriate to the language game being played and in realizing that one must understand the activity of life or context in which the language game is played. In other words, one must understand the form of life, the general activity, in order to understand the language game. However, he stands in contrast to Wittgenstein in positing that it is not possible to understand another form of life. He asks,

. . . how can any one of us know whether or not he is a member of the same interpretive community as any other of us? The answer is that he can't, since any evidence brought forward to support the claim would itself be an interpretation (especially if the "other" were an author long dead). The only "proof" of membership is fellowship, the nod of recognition from someone in the same community. . . . I say it to you now, knowing full well that you will agree with me (that is, understand) only if you already agree with me.Footnote111

Thus it is that the critic is sealed off from author, or should I say that Fish is sealed off from the critic.Footnote112 If this doesn't leave him open to the charge of solipsism, I don't know what would. One must be within Fish's paradigm to understand him because for Fish it is impossible to reason one's way in. But are not his critics, many of whom are also professors of literature, within the same interpretive community who share a particular paradigm? Fish's perspective or paradigm is rather a way of seeing. And here Fish's thought is exemplary of post-modernism.

The problem with this theory is that it proves too much. It proves that anyone who is a member of the same interpretive community will not disagree on interpretation. And indeed, if the critic were so constrained by his community that he were unable to have any latitude in interpretation, then all with similar cultures and backgrounds would agree. But as we know they do not. Fish might respond to this by saying that yes there is some freedom to have differing interpretations, but it is freedom sanctioned or doled out by the institution, thus removing himself from criticism once again, proving himself to be the slippery fellow that he is.

Wittgenstein would not agree that two differing communities are separated from communication. As we saw earlier the scientist and the religious adherent are not unable to communicate, they can communicate but the "proofs" for each discipline are inappropriate to the other. This is the point of claiming that language games have family resemblance's as it makes communication possible. Furthermore, his example of why we call something a "number" reminds us that it has a relationship to other things that have been called number and he draws the analogy of a spinning thread in which fibre is twisted upon fibre. We can use this idea to criticize Fish's radical separateness of interpretive communities: just as communities use words and concepts which overlap, so one community can "understand" another by the relatedness of their concepts bearing "family resemblance's" and the similarities of their form of life.

In the real world cultures overlap and few are completely isolated from every other. Even historically speaking our culture is not isolated from the past as our word usage, forms of life, and language games are dependant on those of our ancestors so that there is an overlap between cultures historically. Thus our culture is not completely different from that of Shakespeare, Dante, or even the apostle John. And Fish has not explained how it is that one interpretive community could stop and another begin with complete disjuncture. One of the difficulties with the notion of interpretive community is its ill-defined nature. Fish has not attempted, to my knowledge, to clearly define what such a community is. If meaning is, as Fish maintains in words reminiscent of Wittgenstein, "something acquired in the context of an activity," then why can one not familiarize herself with the context or form of life in order to approximate meaning?

Wittgenstein's idea that language games are founded on forms of life has several implications for Fish's theory. Wittgenstein says, "The common behavior of mankind is the system of reference by means of which we interpret an unknown language."Footnote113 So that another language is only understood insofar as another form of life bears commonality with our own. Wittgenstein maintains, as we have seen, that language games are not totally independent, contra Fish. Even a language that had been isolated for centuries could be interpreted or "understood" because there is commonality in forms of life. Wittgenstein implies here that there is something essential about forms of life at the very least, which implies a kind of pragmatic essentialism in humanity. If there were nothing that one culture held in common with another culture or time period, translation, let alone communication, would not be possible. It is for this reason that Wittgenstein says, "If a lion could talk, we could not understand him."Footnote114 We could not understand him because he does not share our form of life, because its activities are so radically different from ours. Fish maintains contra Wittgenstein that other cultures bear nothing in common with our own, especially those long dead. They are to us as lions. But fortunately distant cultures and time periods are not as radically different as Fish's theory assumes. Wittgenstein is correct in that there is a "common behavior of mankind."


Determined Communities

Fish's thinking about interpretive communities leans toward a strong determinism. Fish as we saw earlier maintained that readers do not have their own strategies, rather they flow from the interpretive community and "at once enable and limit the operations of his consciousness."Footnote115 The individual is determined by his cultural assumptions and unable to step outside "of his own convictions and beliefs."

But that is the one thing a historically conditioned consciousness cannot do--scrutinize its own beliefs, conduct a rational examination of its own convictions--for in order to begin such a scrutiny, it would first have to escape the grounds of its own possibility, and it could only do that if it were not historically conditioned and were instead an acontextual or unsituated entity. . ."Footnote116

The question naturally arises then, "How do you know?" Fish's determinism is self-stultifying. If readers are determined by their cultural contexts to read with certain pre-defined conceptual grids and are unable to scrutinize their own beliefs, how would Fish ever know this? Gerald Graff makes this very point in response to Fish, he "does not see that his present position would leave him without a vantage point for coherently stating that view."Footnote117 In order to perceive that communities are historically conditioned one must have an objective, encompassing perspective--which is exactly what Fish claims we do not and can not have.

This view of the interpretive community is a much too monolithic, reductionist view which does not square with what we know by experience.Footnote118 Members of the same "interpretive community" approach a text with "an indefinite number of incompatible, mutually exclusive, conflicting, or different ways of talking that are consistent with our peculiar background assumptions or with the theoretical and practical constraints on our practice," as Battersby has put it.Footnote 119


The Reader-Response Theory of Stanley Fish

How would new insights be brought into an interpretive community and how would individuals with similar backgrounds ever disagree over textual interpretations?

Fish, I believe, has failed to make his point with any philosophical rigor, nor do his theories stand up to a comparison with those philosophers who have demonstrated such rigor. Fish's theories are certainly creative but they are not internally consistent and this is the ultimate test of any theory, not whether it can stand up to a "foundationalist" critique but whether or not it can succeed on its own terms. This it does not do. This leaves me with the final task in my stated goals: to examine Fish's thinking against the sociological backdrop of post-modernism to which we now turn.


Modernism: A Sociological Approach

At this point I would like to examine some of the influences of modernism, from a sociological perspective, on hermeneutical theory and the discipline of literary criticism, especially as it relates to the work of Stanley Fish. Most of this analysis, and even the approach itself, is indebted directly or indirectly to Peter Berger's seminal work, The Homeless Mind. Following Max Weber he defines modernization as "the growth and diffusion of a set of institutions rooted in the transformation of the economy by means of technology."Footnote120 The rise of the modern state finds a number of carriers of modernity, among them are technological production, capitalism, and urbanization, factors that are also major lines of continuity between modernism and post-modernism. These institutions affect the way in which we view and interact with the world. I will attempt to examine some of the influences of these carriers of modernity on the field of literary criticism.

"Historically, the modernizing institutions par excellence have been modern industrial capitalism and the modern bureaucratic state," according to Berger.Footnote121 These modernizing factors have contributed to a shift in the understanding of concepts such as authority and truth a shift similar to that experienced in philosophy which has moved from an emphasis on universal essence to the existing individual. Sociologically these factors can be seen primarily in the political and economic arena in which power is no longer vested in the divine right to rule but with the consent of the governed.

The rise of capitalism has dramatically changed the old hierarchical institutions controlled by church and king and has given rise to modern democracy. Capitalism's ability to "universalize" the market has undermined the hierarchy of the past and brought about a new world. Jane Tompkins catalogs the change in literature, with specific reference to her reader-response perspective, as a result of the changed social order brought on by capitalism:

But, once authors become dependent for their means of support upon the sales of their printed work, the personal relation to their audience is severed and the relationship becomes more purely economic. Manuscripts no longer circulate by hand among a coterie of friends and associates; poems are no longer read aloud in groups; sonnets are not exchanged among acquaintances. Instead, literature assumes the fixed condition of print. The literary work becomes endlessly reproducible, available to anyone who can read. Hence, the possible distance in time and space between the originator of the work and its readers becomes virtually limitless.Footnote122

This certainly has implications for the way in which a work is interpreted. Anthony Thiselton commenting on the rise of reader-response theory says, "In a commercial world too, the consumer decides what is to be offered and what is marketable, and what is marketable becomes 'what is'."Footnote123 What the consumer wants becomes what is true as the power lies with the purchaser, the demand with the consumer. This brings us to the influences of democracy which follow upon capitalism and bring another set of factors to bear on the interpreter. But first let us examine some of the influences of modernity on truth and authority.


The Death of Authority

"God is dead."
-Nietzsche

It is a political Democracy that most accurately reflects the conventional beliefs regarding language and truth as its laws and social mores are, at least theoretically, determined by consensus. Capitalism and Democracy having brought about the demise of the old order based on a transcendent authority, promote an authority rooted in the people. It is an authority that is universal and like the marketplace rests on capital. Thus the old authority rooted in God, in transcendent unchanging principles, has given way to a new order founded upon rationality which in a Democratic society often degenerates into popular opinion, a fear with which Plato was not unfamiliar. The new order stands against the old with its authority rooted in the transcendent. It rebels against any sort of hierarchy either in society, the market, or the academy. As Gadamer has pointed out, the denigration of authority was a prejudice established in the enlightenment.Footnote124

This anti-hierarchical sentiment finds expression in philosophical terms through the death of the Author. Nietzsche proclaimed that God was dead and it was not long after that the notion of an author lost its meaning. Thus the demise of the Author has led to the demise of the author in the field of literature. Roland Barthes has written that "to refuse to fix meaning is, in the end, to refuse God. . . "Footnote125. The post-modern society would prefer an unfixed, conventional view of language and truth because what is not "fixed" can be changed. And it can be changed because the power to do so resides with the society or the interpretive community.

Thus Fish is able to claim with Foucault that the author is a creation of the reader. He is a fiction which is easier to live with than without. But ultimately Fish would claim there is no author because to quote Barthes, "To give a text an Author is to impose a limit on that text, to furnish it with a final signified, to close the writing."Footnote126 Once an author is conceded then an authority figure stands over the reader, alternately approving or condemning whatever meaning the reader takes from the text. She is no longer free and equal but instead subordinate to the will of the author, an authority figure reflective of Western patriarchal society.Footnote127 Conversely, to deprive a text of its author is to deprive it of its intentionality as well as its meaning which makes it easier for a hermeneutic such as Fish's to appear.

Democracy is a value laden institution. It consciously promotes individual freedom, self rule, and equality and these values in turn affect the way we look at the world. America, especially, has seen an increased emphasis placed on individual freedom, the ability to choose one's own destiny, with its right to "life, liberty, and the pursuit happiness" often to the detriment of social responsibility. These values affect the way we look at the world and produce an anti-hierarchical and anti-authoritarian zeitgeist as the power resides with the people. David Wells says that it is "not simply a political system but an entire worldview and for whom, therefore, culture and truth belong to the people."Footnote128


Privatization of Truth

In Berger's analysis of modernity he contends that the individual in modern society lives in a "plurality of life-worlds," by which he means that one's life is fragmented into various differing parts without the ability of each of those parts to interact with one another. Therefore the typical worker's occupation will seldom if ever come into contact with his family life. This scenario can be, and is, multiplied in a world of increasing complexity. "A fundamental aspect of this pluralization is the dichotomy of private and public spheres."Footnote129 Thus the distinction between public and private life becomes a reality in the modern world.

One of the effects of pluralization is, in Berger's analysis, secularization and the privatization of religion. Because religion cannot compete in a pluralistic society, while maintaining peace and harmonious relationships, it becomes increasingly a matter for discussion at home, although this is more the case for American than European communities. The same processes at work to take religious discussion out of the public arena (freedom of religion as seen in the separation of church and state is one of our most cherished values) have also worked to take notions of "truth" from the public arena. As with religion, "truth" has become privatized and expressions like "what is true for me" become commonplace. The very idea that one religion could be true for me while another is true for you, undermines the concept of truth as an objective reality, something which was highly prized under the rubric of modernism. Thus in the post-modern world, the concept of truth becomes private property or immanent. The privatization of which I am referring goes hand in hand with the values of a democratic institution.

One of the results of "cognitive bargaining" in the modern world as a result of the dichotomy between public and private worlds is the subjectivization of truth. One may wonder whether the roots of existential thought cannot be traced to the rise of modernity, which is not to say that it is an asymmetric relationship. (That is not to say strictly that modernism produced existentialism, but that each affected and fed off of the other.) Referring to the fragmentation of the modern identity due to the loss of a cohering world, Berger says, "The modern individual's experience of a plurality of social worlds relativizes every one of them. Consequently the institutional order undergoes a certain loss of reality. . . . the individual's experience of himself becomes more real to him than his experience of the objective social world. Therefore, the individual seeks to find his 'foothold' in reality in himself rather than outside himself."Footnote130 This puts the modern emphasis on existence over essence in a new light. It is not surprising then to find religion, philosophy, and literary theory placing the emphasis more on subjective experience and working to validate that experience. As W. John Harker has said:

So it was that the world seemed less certain. The philosophical reality of logical positivism the psychological certainty of behaviorism, the linguistic "common sense" of sensorially received language, and even the unassailable objectivity of scientific method all fell before competing movements in their respective disciplines, movements which had in common an appeal to the inner consciousness of man as the determiner of relative meaning, rather than an appeal to external observable, analyzable phenomena as the determiners of an objective reality.Footnote131

As truth has become privatized, knowledge has undergone a correlative process of democratization. Whereas at one time truth belonged to the transcendent realm that was fixed and unchanging, it has in the post-modern world become immanent. Knowledge, as with everything else in a capitalistic society, is spoken of in terms of "ownership." This is not a coincidence. Whereas democracy begins with an ontological egalitarianism (that is, all people are equal beings), when transcendence is lost, epistemological egalitarianism results, in which each person has an equal right to make truth claims. Thus the proliferation of opinion polls in which the opinions of those less "informed" are equal to those more "informed," in which the unreflected upon opinions are weighted equally with those that are carefully considered. And it is often these kinds of opinion polls that determine, indirectly, public policy. Likewise, talk shows have become increasingly popular as they have become increasingly ludicrous and regardless of their claim, each one is on an equal footing epistemologically as "everyone has a right to an opinion." Again, Thiselton referring to the rise of reader-oriented hermeneutics says, "Such a move also coheres too neatly with the trend towards social egalitarianism in an age which transfers any notion of 'privileged' knowledge on the part of an author or a sacred text to the shared contributions of pluralist reading communities."Footnote132

It is exactly this privilege knowledge that Stanley Fish's theory transfers to the possession of the reading community. For Fish it is the reader's perspective within his own context that is normative. As the concept of "author" has gone by the wayside there is therefore no longer any need to access what the meaning was in its original context, the reader's context takes precedent. Indeed, for Fish the reader's context is all that is accessible. It is not surprising therefore that Fish's theory would be labeled subjective by his critics, a criticism Fish strongly denies. Peter Kivy maintains that subjectivity is exactly one of the consequences of Fish's critical theory. Appropriately he says that once a reader sees things from Fish's perspective there are no longer any constraints:

For once one sees . . . that the 'rules' and 'procedures' of criticism are not the universal rules and procedures for finding out the truth of some matter or other, but the changeable rules and procedures for making things. . . one will hardly take the rules and procedures as presently constituted, as overriding constraints on what one can or cannot make of a text. . .Footnote133

Once the "myth" of objective and attainable truth has been exploded, there is no longer a belief in a truth that can be obtained by reason. Reason is just another attempt at "metanarrative," another attempt by the powerful to control societal values. Instead truth is a socially constructed cultural given. Truth becomes immanent residing in each individual culture or person. No one has any greater claim to truth than any other as each is on an equal status epistemologically. As Stanley Fish says,

. . . the claims of objectivity and subjectivity can no longer be debated because the authorizing agency, the center of interpretive authority, is at once both and neither. An interpretive community is not objective because as a bundle of interests, of particular purposes and goals, its perspective is interested rather than neutral; but by the very same reasoning the meanings and texts produced by an interpretive community are not subjective because they do not proceed from an isolated individual but from a public and conventional point of view.Footnote134

As we saw earlier, language and literature become a means of promoting ideology as each community represents its own interested viewpoint. Eagleton, a Marxist, claims that literature has always been the means of enforcing a particular ideology on a people for the purposes of exploitation. "Literature, in the meaning of the word we have inherited, is an ideology. It has the most intimate relations to questions of social power."Footnote135 And he discerns this perspective in the work of others such as Jacques Derrida, "deconstruction is for him an ultimately political practice, an attempt to dismantle the logic by which a particular system of thought, and behind that a whole system of political structures and social institutions, maintains its force."Footnote136 If nothing else, at least literary criticism has become an arena in which ideological warfare is waged. Thus Marxist, feminist, African-American and every other interpretive grid competes for validity in the democratic market. It is probably no mistake that each has seated itself in a pedagogical role because in a democracy legitimation comes through the will of the people and education is one of the principle keys to that will.


Pluralism and The Rise of Relativism

Democracy coupled with another carrier of modernization, urbanization, has worked to promote pluralism in the modern world. The West has in the past fifty years seen a staggering increase in contact with other cultures, influenced as well by technological advances which have made such contact easier. It is increasingly acknowledged that we live in a "global village." Chicago boasts a greater population of Poles than does Warsaw. Rogers Park on the North side of the city is said to be one of the most ethnically diverse neighborhoods in the country where over one hundred languages are spoken. This ethnic differentiation, which contributes to an already fragmented society, provides the opportunity for contact with various cultures, their religions, as well as their national literature.

One of the results of this increased contact has been to dethrone the assumed superiority of our own culture. Berger states that "pluralization has a secularizing effect" because the individual is forced to take cognizance of others who do not believe what he believes and whose life is dominated by different, sometimes contradictory, meanings, values and beliefs."Footnote137 These differing if not contradictory meanings, values, and beliefs lead to a cognitive bargaining in which each one's beliefs become less certain, in which more latitude is given to opinions that differ and which leads to the notion that truth is relative to one's socio-historical perspective. Thus, much of the Western ideology has come under attack, ironically from those within the culture. Pluralism and relativism have produced a widespread hesitancy to affirm anything whose origin is in Western culture while at the same time maintaining an obsequious posture toward minority and non-Western ideas. Berger calls this a "failure of nerve" and maintains that, "It is not the first time in history that a cultural elite has stood in the forefront of those who would give up their society."Footnote138

It is by no means accidental that Fish's reader-response thesis has arisen in such a pluralistic age. Even in the academy there are numerous and competing schools of thought. Graff comments that "Fish's concept of interpretive communities was enormously suggestive. . . particularly in an age of competitive academic interpretive schools. . .".Footnote139 As this cognitive bargaining takes place between cultures and viewpoints a certain leveling occurs on the epistemological plain. It becomes more plausible to maintain such a thesis as Fish's.

Harker in chronicling the decline of New Criticism due to its narrow views of literature and heavily pedagogical nature makes an insightful statement. "Yet these internal flaws may not in themselves have been sufficient to bring down the New Criticism had they not become increasingly apparent during a period when public verse and public criticism were becoming antithetical to the increasingly introspective, relativistic spirit of the times."Footnote140

Fish's critical theory accurately reflects this relativistic spirit of the times. The idea that truth is an historically conditioned notion that does not transcend cultural boundaries is by definition relativism.

Within a community, however, a standard of right (and wrong) can always be invoked because it will be invoked against the background of a prior understanding as to what counts as a fact, what is hearable as an argument, what will be recognized as a purpose, and so on. The point, as I shall later write, is that standards of right and wrong do not exist apart from assumptions, but follow from them, and, moreover, since we ourselves do not exist apart from assumptions, a standard of right and wrong is something we can never be without.

Fish's writing smacks of relativism and indeed it is something of which he has often been accused. James Battersby points this out in his article "Professionalism, Relativism, and Rationality" published by the Modern Language Association. It is interesting to note however that Fish believes that he has insulated himself from the critique of relativism by positing his interpretive community theory. In an introduction to one of his reprinted articles in Is There a Text in This Class? he maps some of the course his mental activities have gone through over the years. He says,

I was thus flirting with a relativism that would be removed only when the notion of interpretive communities, grounded in a bedrock of belief, allowed me to preserve the distinction between the fictional and the true by understanding it as a conventional or community-specific distinction rather than as one rooted in nature and eternity.

It is as if he believes that group relativism is any less relativistic than what occurs on an individual basis. But regardless of whether it is relativism prompted by one's subjective consciousness or endorsed as a group activity relativism is still relativism by any other name. As one of Fish's critics wryly comments, "I find no comfort in the fact that my arbitrary assumptions come from an institution rather than from myself."Footnote141

But relativism as a philosophical perspective or hermeneutic presents a number of other problems. David Hackett Fischer in his book Historian's Fallacies shows even less patience with this form of error than he does most others. Fish's argument for the ungroundedness of the interpretive community, which takes full flower in his article entitled, "Anti-Professionalism," leaves itself open to the critique of historicism, that whatever is is right.Footnote142 And Gerald Graff levels this very critique against him in his response to "Anti-Professionalism." But Dr. Fischer appropriately comments that the end result of such a view is that, "It would prevent any moral judgment against the filth which flowed from 'the innermost individual character' of many Nazi beings."Footnote143 If, with Fish and the post-moderns, we are unwilling to apply any transhistorical standards to our or any other cultures' conduct we have fully embraced relativism.

Relativism, regardless of the form, comes under the age old criticism of being a false objectivity. As Battersby has said, "the view that all our ideas are historically or professionally conditioned is itself not historically or professionally conditioned."Footnote144 In other words, relativism claims that all truth is relative except for the claim that "truth is relative." And here we are in the same predicament the post-modern critics want to free us from, that is a metanarrative, a story that explains all other stories. But maybe Fish will argue that of course relativism is only my socially constructed reality, true only for the culture in which I live. This then is an agnostic position regarding possibility of knowing truth instead of the claim to knowledge which relativism definitely makes.

Fish's response to this criticism of his position is to argue again that the critic is hopelessly mired in his own foundationalist paradigm.Footnote145 His claim is that it is illegitimate for the foundationalist to criticize his position because the foundationalist belongs to a different community with different interpretive assumptions and his position can only be understood from within Fish's position. Battersby responds,

My answer, of course, is that self-refutation owes no special allegiance to foundationalism or essentialism. As a standard, it serves many causes on many fronts. It belongs to the class of transparadigmatic criteria. . . . it has our interest because it is a strong standard, capable of leading to a deep objection.

If we are willing to engage in anti-rationalist practices by denying the principle of self-contradiction, as Derrida is and as Fish is apparently wont to do, we are in grave danger. Fortunately, the danger and mortality will belong to the position that is in contradiction with our form of life.Footnote146

One of dangerous aspects of relativism is that it bears an element of truth. It is certainly true that one's perspective and context controls, to a large extent, one's opinion. It is also true that different cultures and time periods emphasize different standards depending again on their cultural context. It does not however follow that all truth is relative. The relativist attempts to reason from what appears true in specific cases to what is true universally. This is both fallacious and self-stultifying.

Berger draws an interesting insight in The Homeless Mind that I believe applies to philosophical relativism and post-modern thought. His thesis is that modernity has caused a homelessness that is deeper than social dislocation.

The 'homelessness' of modern social life has found its most devastating expression in the area of religion. . . . The age-old function of religion--to provide ultimate certainty amid the exigencies of the human condition--has been severely shaken. Because of the religious crisis in modern society, social "homelessness" has become metaphysical--that is, it has become "homelessness" in the cosmos.

It is at this very time of metaphysical homelessness that post-modern theories such as Fish's with his focus on the individual reader's consciousness and the ungrounded nature of interpretive communities has appeared.

Post-modern literary criticisms fit nicely into the new intellectual paradigm. While Deconstructionism works to undermine classical Western thought based on the principle of non-contradiction, reader-response theories serve to legitimate whatever interpretive paradigm a particular "interpretive community" brings to the text. Thiselton writes, "If reader-oriented literary theory has become entangled with philosophical contextual relativism and post-modernism, meanings of texts are not only contingently plural in the history of interpretation and textual reception; they are irreducibly plural in principle as a hermeneutical axiom."Footnote147 Thus pluralism is the order of the day. And it is no accident that reader-oriented hermeneutics sprang up at a time of increased pluralism. In a pluralistic world it is difficult to maintain any kind of traditional value structure as contact with other cultures inevitably leads to "cognitive bargaining," in which the ideas of each culture contaminate that of the other.Footnote148

Pluralism, then has influenced this epistemological crisis in thinking whereby no group of people, at least those "properly" educated, are willing to pass judgment on another culture, thereby claiming implicitly a superiority of one culture to another. Relativism and modern language theory as well contribute to the current situation. There is no longer a belief in a truth that can be obtained by reason, as reason is just another attempt at "metanarrative." Instead truth is a socially constructed cultural given. Truth becomes immanent residing in each individual culture or person. No one has any greater claim to truth than any other as each is on an equal status. But the free-market of ideas is not necessarily a bad market to be in as long as some criterion exists for establishing truth. But once reason is thrown out as a fair and impartial judge, no purchasing power remains in the market except by power or consensus (this is the very point of modern language theory--"truth" exists only by consensus).


What is Man?

L'homme n'est qu'une passion inutile. Jean-Paul Sartre

Many views have been postulated regarding the nature of man. What kind of being is he and how does he fit into the universe. So it is interesting to note this arose at about the time of the industrial revolution. It is also this view which dominated literary criticism, with its mechanistic view of interpretation, until recently. It was this notion that the Romantics rebelled against, positing an alternative of man as organism or part of nature, and it is this notion also that the post-moderns seek to replace with another view. Stanley Fish astutely observes that the difference between Stylistics or formalism and his own reader-response analysis is ". . . more that an procedural distinction; for at its heart are different notions of what it is to read which are finally different notions of what it is to be human."Footnote149

What kind of notion would the post-moderns assert for the "essence" of man? It has been long recognized that man bears the unique faculty of language bearer. Past notions often viewed language as reflective of a transcendent realm. Thus man's language bore a "real presence," a presence which gave intimations of his connection with the divine. Current notions, however, regard language as conventional and in turn regard man as ultimately ungrounded and free-floating. His being is not connected to a divine reality or any reality at all other than that which he is able to create. Thus man is uniquely able to create meaning in his world as he is able to create language. Fish comments, "The ability to interpret is not acquired; it is constitutive of being human."Footnote150 In other words, man has the unique capacity to create meaning as Fish has said elsewhere.

The modern worldview brought with it a view of truth that centered around rationality and the scientific method. The widespread and undeniable practical success of the sciences effected a change in most other disciplines to meet the challenge of scientific truth. Thus humanities as well as theology, at one time called the "Queen of the sciences,"Footnote151 felt the need to appropriate this method in their own disciplines in order to make their "professions" legitimate. In literary studies this gave rise to a more objective New Critical approach to textual interpretation. Tompkins provides critical analysis of this,

Literary studies, consequently, whose subject matter is not quantifiable, whose methods are not formalized, and whose results are not able to be objectively verified, cannot compete with science for an equal share of prestige and economic support in a society where positivist values prevail. This line of argument suggests that the only way to defend the literary enterprise would be to challenge the positivist conceptual framework on which science depends for its prestige. And in fact, this is what reader-response criticism, in its later phase, has done.Footnote152

Stanley Fish, who is married to Jane Tompkins, similarly regards his predecessors in critical theory as fawning over the sciences. "Stylistics, in short, is an attempt to put criticism on a scientific basis," he says. And as Tompkins points out, this is exactly what he seeks to undermine by challenging the possibility of objectivity, the empirical method and by cutting himself off from any "evidentiary procedures" which might lend support to his theory.Footnote153

It might be argued however that the positivistic conceptual framework has fallen on hard times apart from literary criticism and that the reason New Criticism gave way was not because it failed but because "post-modernism" has ushered in a new paradigm by which all disciplines should be measured.


Conclusion: Back to Babel

Let us build ourselves a city and a tower with its top in the heavens and make a name for ourselves. . . Genesis

I hope that it can be seen from the preceding analysis that the values of modern literary theory have not come about without sociological and philosophical influences. I have attempted to examine one post-modern or post-structuralist critical theory in light of some of the factors that have contributed to the rise of what is now called post-modernism. Contemporary critical theory and specifically that of Stanley Fish can be understood in terms of changes that have occurred in philosophical thought going back at least to the Enlightenment. Current thinking in the literary field, as well as others, is also influenced by sociological changes such as the rise of the modern state and an increasingly pluralistic society.

The changes that I have attempted to examine in brief have brought about a revolution in thought, one that is commonly compared with the revolution that took place during the Enlightenment. Our generation is witnessing the demise of the Enlightenment project's relentless pursuit of objectivity. The demise of this hope has ushered in a reevaluation of Western rationality which is often labeled ideological and no more reflective of reality than any other system of thought. Existence or "Being" having gained ascendancy over essence has found itself without the nobility of purpose with which it was endowed by those same essentialist theories. Truth is therefore considered conventional instead of foundational. And man is no longer certain of who he is.

These conventional notions of truth are encouraged by a pluralistic, democratic society that is oriented around the consumer. As governmental authority has ceased to reside in a supposed divine prerogative, so to have notions of truth. Truth is no longer seen as a reflection of a transcendent realm but as that which is immanent and conventionally determined. It is public opinion that determines what is right and the group with the most purchasing power in the system is the group in control. Again, public opinion is what is important because in a pluralistic society the loss of certainly does not stop with religious issues, moral issues and the very idea of truth are called into question and it is only public opinion that is left to determine between competing views.

It is amidst this confusing cacophony of voices that Stanley Fish's reader-response hermeneutic finds a receptive audience. But I believe that it is apparent that Fish's critical method does not stand up to close examination. And by this I do not mean that it fails in a world of foundationalist presuppositions. Any truth claim, to borrow an idea from Francis Schaeffer, must be both internally consistent and livable. Fish's theory is neither. For although he claims that his is only a theoretical construct without implications, his theory does have implications.

I have criticized Fish on a number of different levels. Hermeneutically, one of Fish's first moves is to locate meaning in the reading community a move which, while it coheres nicely with post-modern thought, lends itself to subjectivity in interpretive theory. In this model the hermeneutical circle is a vicious circle in which no progress or new insight can be had that is not simply an explication of the individual or the group's mindset.

But Fish has also failed to define carefully enough exactly what constitutes a interpretive community. Because he has failed to do this, his theory enables him to assume a radical disjuncture between interpretive communities that does not reflect the world in which we live. To apply Wittgenstein's analogy of the relatedness of words, communities are interrelated phenomena in which a single individual may have membership within numerous differing communities. If interpretive communities were as "monolithic" as Fish seems to purport, there would then be no basis for differing interpretations within the same interpretive community. But fortunately, there are differences.

Another implication of Fish's theory is that which arises from his loose theory of conventionalism. He appears to reason, following after philosophers and linguists such as Wittgenstein, that language is conventional and because language is conventional and not transcendent that what it refers to is conventional and not transcendent, a mistake that Wittgenstein and others do not make. Were this the case, that communities construct their own realities without reference to any "transhistorical" or transparadigmatic categories, philosophical relativism would be the logical result. Because Fish's theory tends toward this kind of view of conventionalism, his thinking lends itself to a subjective view of truth and an evaluation of reason as ideological.

Finally, his theory in its implications severs the critical enterprise from the moorings of "false" notions of truth and allows each interpretive community to be an isolated enterprise without the need to justify its theory to any other community as each group constitutes its own world. Indeed, with belief in reason as transparadigmatic, it is senseless to attempt to justify one form of life to another.

Fish's conventionalism has returned critical theory to Babel. Each group speaks its own language in isolation and without the ability to understand any other group. But there is one important difference between Fish's thinking and the story of ancient Babel: in Fish's Babel each group is under the mistaken notion that they understand the others. However, for Fish to be able to enlighten us regarding topography of Babel would require him to have a perspective that is transparadigmatic, it would require Fish to be able to scale Babel's tower and survey the landscape. Unfortunately, the tower Fish has attempted to scale has proven to be notoriously difficult to complete. Thus Fish comes under the same criticism he himself launched, by proclaiming the community dependent nature of all truth-claims he has torn down any possible perspective from which he could make this claim. Fish has kicked the tower out from beneath himself.


Footnotes

Footnote1

Kevin Vanhoozer, "Aesthetic Theology," Trinity Journal, n.s., 8 (Spring 1987): 43.

Footnote2

Jane P. Tompkins, Reader Response Criticism (Baltimore: Hohns Hopkins University Press, 1980), 223.

Footnote3

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. (New York: Crossroad Publishing, 1989), 185.

Footnote4

Martin Heidegger, Being and Time (Oxford: Blackwell, 1962), 5; quoted in Anthony Thiselton, Two Horizons (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1980), 26.

Footnote5

Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory: An Introduction (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), 55.

Footnote6

Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), 179.

Footnote7

Vanhoozer, "Aesthetic Theology," 37.

Footnote8

Heidegger, Being and Time, 188-189.

Footnote9

Eagleton, Literary Theory, 66. One may question Eagleton's evaluation at this point as Heidegger refers to understanding as arising out of "letting language, from within language, speak to us" (emphasis mine).

Footnote10

Brice R. Wachterhauser, Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy (New York: Staty University of New York Press, 1991), 31.

Footnote11

If one understands Gadamer as positing an Hegelian dialectic between the text and the reader, then the synthesis which occurs would not negate the original sense of the text in its original context but would incorporate this into the reader's context. Thus Gadamer would appear to call for an understanding of both "meaning" and "significance," to use Hirsch's terms.

Footnote12

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Garrett Broden and John Cumming, 2d ed., (New York: Crossroad, 1982), 353; quoted in Grant Osborne, The Hermeneutical Spiral (Downers Grove, Illinois: InterVarsity Press, 1991), 370.

Footnote13

Gadamer, Truth and Method, 350.

Footnote14

K. M. Newton, "Hermeneutics and Modern Literary Criticism," British Journal of Aesthetics 29, (Spring 1989): 117.

Footnote15

Eagleton, Literary Theory, 47.

Footnote16

W. K. Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley, The Intentional Fallacy," chap. in The Verbal Icon: Studies in the Meaning of Poetry (Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1954), 194.

Footnote17

Ibid., 196.

Footnote18

Wimsatt, The Verbal Icon, 21; quoted in Tompkins, Reader-Response Criticism, 223.

Footnote19

Krentz comments in his discussion of Bultmann that, "History is in danger of being interiorized and psychologized." The Historical-Critical Method (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1975), 31.

Footnote20

Ibid., 31.

Footnote21

Eagleton, Literary Theory, 74.

Footnote22

Wachterhauser, p. 38.

Footnote23

Eagleton, Literary Theory, 74. This is somewhat of an odd comment, albeit ideologically charged.

Footnote24

Wofgang Iser, "The Reading Proscess: A Phenomenological Approach," in Reader Response Criticism, ed. Jane P. Tompkins (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980), 50.

Footnote25

Stanley Fish, "Literature in the Reader," in Reader-Response Criticism, 82.

Footnote26

Ibid., 98.

Footnote27

Fish, "Interpreting the Variorium," in Reader-Response Criticism, 183.

Footnote28

Fish eventually came to see the contradiction in maintaining an anti-intentionalist stance while attempting to demonstrate Milton's rhetorical techniques. Stanley Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?: The Authority of Interpretive Communities (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), 7.

Footnote29

Ibid., 147.

Footnote30

Ibid.27.

Footnote31

Ibid., 150.

Footnote32

J. F. Worthen, "On the Matter of the Text," University of Toronto Quarterly 60 (Spring 1991): 339.

Footnote33

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class? 158.

Footnote34

Ibid., 32.

Footnote35

Ibid., 44.

Footnote36

Ibid., 43.

Footnote37

Fish tends to use the same device that he attributed to Milton earlier, that is, he loves to surprise the reader and he often does this by equivocation on terms. He would of course say that this bolsters his own conclusion that we read ourselves into the text.

Footnote38

Cf. p272

Footnote39

Ibid., 13.

Footnote40

Ibid., 68.

Footnote41

Ibid., 105.

Footnote42

Fish's own work has demonstrated this thesis, at least to himself.

Footnote43

Robert Scholes, Textual Powers: Literary Theory and the Teaching of English (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985), 152. The irony here of course is that Rorschach ink blots are intended to illicit certain responses from the viewers.

Footnote44

Worthen, "On the Matter of the Text," 350.

Footnote45

Fish, Is There A Text In This Class? 163.

Footnote46

Ibid., 16.

Footnote47

John 20:31.

Footnote48

Ibid., 152.

Footnote49

Ibid., 14.

Footnote50

Ibid., 174.

Footnote51

Ibid., 97.

Footnote52

Ibid., 303-4.

Footnote53

Ibid., 11.

Footnote54

Stanley Fish, "Anti-Professionalism," New Literary History 17 (1985): 97.

Footnote55

See Fish, "Anti-Professionalism," 93; and Is There a Text in This Class?, 97.

Footnote56

Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, p. 42.

Footnote57

Newbigin here reveals his fideistic assumptions, not completely unlike many post-modern thinkers, p. 29. Cf. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, pp 41e. "It may easily look as if every doubt merely revealed an existing gap in the foundations; so that secure understanding is only possible if we first doubt everything that can be doubted, and then remove all these doubts." In On Certainty he says, "If you tried to doubt everything you would not get as far as doubting anything. The game of doubting itself presupposes certainty" (sec. 115). Wittgenstein takes a practical approach by securing the foundations of language and thought in "forms of life."

Footnote58

Shiv Kumar, "Toward a Theory of Romanticism," British Romantic Poets, New York: New York University Press, 1966, p. 6.

Footnote59

Copleston, v. IX, p. 335.

Footnote60

Rollo May, Abraham Maslow, et. al., Existential Psychology, Random House, New York, 1961, p. 16.

Footnote61

Kierkegaard, p. 42.

Footnote62

Milan Kundera, responding to Nietsche's comment, said about his book The Unbearable Lightness of Being, "If God is gone and man is no longer master, then who is master? The planet is moving through the void without any master. There it is, the unbearable lightness of being." Quoted in Veith, Reading Between the Lines, p. 209. see Kundera pp 5-6

Footnote63

Veith, Postmodern Times, p. 38.

Footnote64

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 158, Cf. p. 28, p. 33, p. 65, p. 159

Footnote65

Ibid., p. 86.

Footnote66

Ibid., p.94.

Footnote67

Ibid., p 177.

Footnote68

Berger, A Far Glory, p.18.

Footnote69

Wittgenstein, On Certainty, sec. 559, p. 73e

Footnote70

Cf. Derrida, Jacques, Structure, "Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences", The Structuralist Controversy, eds. Macksey and Donato, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1970, pp. 247-265.

Footnote71

Ibid., p. 249.

Footnote72

I am indebted here to Alan Jacobs fine article "Deconstruction" in Contemporary Literary Theory, eds. Clarence Walhout and Leland Ryken, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans Publishing, 1991, pp. 172-198.

Footnote73

Tompkins, p. 226

Footnote74

Eagleton, p. 188-198.

Footnote75

The parallels with George Orwell's 1984 are frightening. What is worse, however, is the deterministic attitude this language theory produces. One might well reason, "someone has to control the language ergo it might as well be us."

Footnote76

Tompkins, p. xxv.

Footnote77

It is also interesting to note that academic language and writing today is often self-referential, self-conscious meta-discourse which makes obvious the writer as writer and perspective as perspective. In this way it attempts to avoid the concealed totalitarianism of writing that assumes its author who remains hidden.

Footnote78

Eagleton, p. 143.

Footnote79

Veith, Postmodern Times, p. 54.

Footnote80

Quoted in Vanhoozer, "Aesthetic Theology," p.35.

Footnote81

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 49

Footnote82

Fish, "Anti-Professionalism," p. 95.

Footnote83

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 89, 97, 310.

Footnote84

See "Anti-Professionalism" where Fish labels Wittgenstein a member of the 'intellectual left" defined as those thinkers who view categories of knowledge as "not natural or given but is conventional and has been instituted by the operation of historical and political forces," pp. 97-98.

Footnote85

Anthony Thiselton compares Wittgenstein with the latter two in The Two Horizons. "Wittgenstein's notion of "language game" has striking parallels with Heidegger's understanding of "world" and even with Gadamer's notion of the interpreter's horizons," p.33.

Footnote86

See also Nicholas F. Gier, Wittgenstein and Phenomenology.

Footnote87

Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, sec..38.

Footnote88

Diogenes Allen interprets this phrase to mean that "words are taken from their place in a form of life." In other words, language can only function properly in the context in which it is part of the form of life. A language game can be transplanted from one form of life to another, but this is to misuse language and it is this misuse which results in so much confusion. Thus it is inappropriate for the language game of religion to use the proofs from the language game of science, and so on. Philosophy for Understanding Theology, p. 268.

Footnote89

Ibid., sec. 491.

Footnote90

Ibid., sec. 421.

Footnote91

Ibid., sec. 43.

Footnote92

Ibid., p. 220e

Footnote93

Ibid., sec. 18.

Footnote94

Ibid., sec. 23.

Footnote95

Ibid., sec. 2.

Footnote96

Ibid., sec. 355.

Footnote97

Ibid., sec. 97.

Footnote98

Gadamer, I believe mistakenly, remarks of Wittgenstein in a later edition of Truth and Method that, "Wittgenstein has thematized [language games] in order to criticize metaphysics," p. 577. Wittgenstein thematized language games in order to criticize the view that language is transcendent. But I believe it is false to reason that because language is conventional and not transcendant that therefore what language refers to cannot be transcendant but always conventional.

Footnote99

Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, sec. 67.

Footnote100

It is important to differentiate Wittgenstein from the logical positivist's verification principle which concludes that what cannot be verified does not exist. Wittgenstein would have held in the Tractatus that unless a statement pictures a "state of affairs" in the world it is without sense not that it fails to correspond to anything at all. On this point Wittgenstein is agnostic. Because words and language pictures "sie119A>Footnote the real world, it simply has no access to a metaphysical. Therefore "What we cannot speak about we must pass over in silence"(p. 74). Wittgenstein does make an exception on this point to the rules of logic (Cf. 6.1222, 6.13, and 6.54). This important exception may have eventually led him to change his language theory for that of the Investigations.

Footnote101

Gier, p. 21. Gier also suggest that Wittgenstein borrowed the idea of Lebensformen from Spengler whom he admired greatly.

Footnote102

Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, sec 97, p.44e.

Footnote103

Fish would, I believe, maintain that this position is naive.

Footnote104

OpCit., p. 226e.

Footnote105

Wittgenstein, On Certainty, sec. 109, 110. Wittgenstein states this in direct contradiction of Descartes.

Footnote106

OpCit., sec. 580.

Footnote107

Ibid., sec. 580.

Footnote108

Ibid., sec. 641.

Footnote109

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 161.

Footnote110

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p 304. What is ironic is that Fish often practices this belief in response to his critics. He often makes himself guilty of equivocating on terms and almost appears to deliberately misinterpret his critics to demonstrate his interpretive freedom. See for instance "A Reply to Gerald Graff" in which he appears to equivocate on Graff's use of the word "determined," p. 120ff. Worthen also comments regarding a different point that Fish, ". . . has proved nothing except the perennial ease of trading on an equivocation," p. 339.

Footnote111

Ibid., p. 173

Footnote112

Cf p304 where he says that, "Communication ocurs only within such a system."

Footnote113

Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, sec. 206.

Footnote114

Ibid., p. 223e.

Footnote115

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 14.

Footnote116

Fish, "Anti-Professionalism," p. 107.

Footnote117

Graff, "Response to Stanley Fish" p. 112.

Footnote118

See also Robert Scholes critique of Fish in Textual Power, pp. 152 ff.

Footnote119

Battersby, p. 54.

Footnote120

Berger, The Homeless Mind, p. 9.

Footnote121

Ibid., p. 102.

Footnote122

Tompkins, p. 222. This is of course no different than ancient times. Any time something is written it is liable to be copied and the author has thereby lost a certain amount of control over the original.

Footnote123

Thiselton, New Horizons, p. 503.

Footnote124

Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 279.

Footnote125

Barthes, "Death of the Author," p. 143. I am indebted to Kevin Vanhoozer for this insight.

Footnote126

Ibid., 147.

Footnote127

But one of the results of Fish's thinking is to sever the author from her words which makes no one responsible for those words. This is however not the way we live, especially in such a politicaly correct ere.

Footnote128

Wells, p.189.

Footnote129

Homeless Mind pp. 64-65.

Footnote130

Berger, The Homeless Mind, p. 77-78. It is interesting to note that Kierkegaard was not only reacting to Hegel but also against cold bureaucratic church of his native Denmark.

Footnote131

Harker p. 363

Footnote132

Thiselton, p. 503.

Footnote133

Kivy, p. 61.

Footnote134

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 14.

Footnote135

Eagleton, p. 22. Cf. Fish, p. 111.

Footnote136

Ibid., p. 148.

Footnote137

Berger, The Homeless Mind, p. 80.

Footnote138

Berger, A Far Glory, p. 64.

Footnote139

Graff, "Response," p. 110.

Footnote140

Harker, p. 362.

Footnote141

Stecker, p. 229.

Footnote142

Fischer, p. 156

Footnote143

Ibid.

Footnote144

Battersby, p.56. Fischer also comments that, ". . . relativists all argued that they and their friends were exempt from relativism in some degree," and cites Cushing Stout that it is "a form of intellectual suicide," p. 42.

Footnote145

Fish, "Resistance and Independence: A Reply to Gerald Graff," p. 119.

Footnote146

See Kivy, p. 64.

Footnote147

Thiselton, New Horizons, p. 473.

Footnote148

The term is Berger's.

Footnote149

Fish, Is There a Text in This Class?, p. 94.

Footnote150

Ibid., p. 172.

Footnote151

While this expression belongs to Aquinas who clearly predates the scientific revolution, it has since been used by theologians to justify their existence in an increasingly scientific age.

Footnote152

Tompkins, p. 222.

Footnote153

Fish's position in this regard is not unlike much Reformed epistemology. Were he arguing in Christian circles he may be labeled a fideist.


Bibliography

Abrams, M. H. "Reader-Response Criticism." A Glossary of Literary Terms. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace College Publishers, 1993.

Allen, Diogenes. Philosophy for Understanding Theology. Atlanta: John Knox Press, 1985.

Battersby, James L. "Professionalism, Relativism, and Rationality." Publication of the Modern Language Association 107 (January 1992): 51-64.

Berger, Peter. The Homeless Mind. New York: Vintage Books, 1974.

______ A Far Glory: The Quest for Faith in an Age of Credulity.

Caputo, John D. "Presidential Address: Radical Hermeneutics and the Human Condition." In Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association Vol. LXII, edited by Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Washington: The American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1988.

Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy. New York: Doubleday, 1993.

Derrida, Jacques, Structure, "Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences", The Structuralist Controversy, eds. Macksey and Donato, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1970, pp. 247-265.

Eagleton, Terry. Literary Theory: An Introduction. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983.

Fischer, David Hackett. Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1970.

Fish, Stanley. Is Their A Text In This Class?: The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980.

Fish, Stanley E. "Interpreting the Variorum." In Reader-Response Criticism, ed. Jane P. Tompkins, 164-184. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980.

______ "Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics." In Reader-Response Criticism, ed. Jane P. Tompkins, 70-100. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980.

______. "Anti-Professionalism." New Literary History 17 (1985): 89-108.

______. "Resistance and Independence: A Reply to Gerald Graff." New Literary History 17 (1985): 119-27.

Foucault, Michel. "What is an Author." Textual Strategies: Perspectives in Post-Structuralist Criticism, ed. Josue V. Harari, 141-160. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1979.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. Second, Revised edition, New York: Crossroad Publishing, 1989.

Gier, Nicholas F. Wittgenstein and Phenomenology. Albany: State University of Albany Press, 1981.

Graff, Gerald. "Interpretation on Tlon: A Response to Stanley Fish." New Literary History 17 (May 1985): 109-17.

______. "The Paradox of the Culture War." The University of Chicago, Chicago.

Harker, W. John. "The New Imperative in Literary Criticism." Visible Language XIX 3 (Summer 1985): 356-72.

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper and Row, 1962.

Jacobs, Alan. "Deconstruction." Contemporary Literary Theory: A Christian Appraisal. ed. Clarence Walhout and Leland Ryken, 172-98. Grand Rapids: W.B. Eerdmans, 1991.

Kierkegaard, Soren Aabye. Fear and Trembling. New York: Viking Penguin Books, 1985.

Kivy, Peter. "Fish's Consequences." The British Journal of Aesthetics 29 (Winter 1989): 57-64.

Kumar, Shiv. "Toward a Theory of Romanticism," British Romantic Poets. New York: New York University Press, 1966.

May, Rollo. Abraham Maslow, et. al., Existential Psychology, Random House, New York, 1961.

Macksey, Richard and Eugenio Donato, eds. The Structuralist Controversy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1970.

Newbigin, Lesslie. Truth to Tell. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing, 1991.

Osborne, Grant R. The Hermeneutical Spiral: A Comprehensive Introduction to Biblical Interpretation. Downers Grove, Illinois: InterVarsity Press, 1991.

Scholes, Robert. Textual Power: Literary Theory and the Teaching of English. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985.

Stecker, Robert. "Fish's Argument for the Relativity of Interpretive Truth." The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48 (Summer 1990): 223-230.

Thiselton, Anthony C. New Horizons in Hermeneutics. Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1992.

______. The Two Horizons: New Testament Hermeneutics and Philosophical Description with Special Reference to Heidegger, Bultmann, Gadamer, and Wittgenstein. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans and Exeter: Paternoster, 1980.

Tompkins, Jane P. Reader-Response Criticism. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980.

Vanhoozer, Kevin. "A Lamp in The Labyrinth: The Hermeneutics of 'Aesthetic' Theology." Trinity Journal, 8 (Spring 1987): 25-56.

_______. Mapping the Maze: Introducing the Postmodern World. 1994 Kenneth Kantzer Lectures. Deerfield, Ill.:Rolfing Library, 1994. Cassette tape.

Veith, Gene Edward. Postmodern Times. Wheaton: Crossway Books, 1994.

______. Reading Between The Lines. Wheaton: Crossway Books, 1990.

Wachterhauser, Brice R., ed. Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy. New York: State University of New York Press, 1986.

Weinsheimer, Joel. Philosophical Hermeneutics and Literary Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991.

Wells, David. No Place for Truth.

Wimsatt, William and Monroe Beardsley, "The Intentional Fallacy."

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. On Certainty. ed., G.E.M. Anscombe, New York: Harper Torch Books, 1972.

______. Philosophical Investigations. trans., G.E.M. Anscombe, New York: Macmillan, 1958.

Worthen, J. F. "On the Matter of the Text." University of Toronto Quarterly 60 (Spring 1991):337-53.

Add new comment

Filtered HTML

  • Web page addresses and e-mail addresses turn into links automatically.
  • Allowed HTML tags: <a> <em> <strong> <cite> <blockquote> <code> <ul> <ol> <li> <dl> <dt> <dd>
  • Lines and paragraphs break automatically.
4 + 0 =
Solve this simple math problem and enter the result. E.g. for 1+3, enter 4.